Why classical myth and autism?

Why classical myth and autism?

The idea for this project started to take shape at a meeting in 2008 with a special needs teacher, who mentioned that, in her experience and those of her colleagues, autistic children often enjoy classical myth. I began to wonder why this might be the case, and whether – as a classicist who researches, and loves, classical myth – there was anything I could contribute. I started this blog to report on my progress which was often sporadic until the launch of the Warsaw-based European Research Council-funded project Our Mythical Childhood (2016-22) to trace the role of classics in children’s culture.

My key contribution to the project is an exploration of classics in autistic children’s culture, above all by producing myth-themed activities for autistic children. This blog shares my progress, often along Herculean paths, including to a book of lessons for autistic children focusing on the Choice of Hercules between two very different paths in life. The image above, illustrating the homepage of this blog, is one of the drawings by Steve K. Simons, the book's illustrator, of a chimneypiece panel in a neoclassical villa at Roehampton in South West London. The lessons centre on this panel.

Thursday 21 November 2013

Classical Studies and Disability Studies


Hephaistos visited by Athena or Thetis
This posting responds to two recent experiences.  The first of these was writing, publishing and then getting some really interesting feedback on my previous blog post, where I expressed my intention to consider how far a disability studies approach to heroes and monsters of classical myth might aid the development of monstrous pedagogies.  The second was contributing a session, 'Classics and Disability Studies', to an MRes 'Theories and Methods' module at Roehampton yesterday evening.  The students were deeply engaged - so much so that the session took on a 'life' of its own that diverged from the notes I had prepared in advance.  Here are those notes, written up but also expanded. 

We began by considering examples of disabled persons from antiquity. I anticipated that the 'obvious' ones would be named such as the doubly-disabled Oedipus (lame from birth and later blind), the lame god Hephaistos, and the Spartan newborns who fell victim to the Spartan programme of eugenics.  These were indeed named, as were others with physical disabilities, including the emperor Claudius, the Homeric non-hero Thersites and the blind prophet Teiresias.  But the students also asked about how to define 'disability' - did it mean physical disability, or could it include, say, mental ill-heath or dyslexia? What about figures who were not regarded as disabled in antiquity but whom we might define as such now: Achilles, being one such example - perfectly bodied, but in the wake of Jonathan Shay's analysis, one of a host of heroes showing traits of Post Traumatic Stress Disorder? We also considered how far disability needs to be seen as something that dis-abled an individual.  For instance:
  • When the Amazons are said to remove one of their breasts are they thought of as disabling themselves or, rather, enabling themselves to perform their roles more successfully? 
  • What about when a disabled individual has different abilities that are developed precisely because he or she is disabled, Hephaistos being a case in point. As I mentioned, on the Parthenon frieze, the god with the most developed musculature is Hephaistos - one way of reading this representation of the god is that, through his physical labour, he meets standards of bodily perfection in ways denied his fellow gods; it is a marker of his difference from the other major gods - in ways I'll build on below.
Issues therefore include these:
  1. How far should a disability studies approach focus on aspects of physical disability?
  2. How far can research into conditions such as ADHD, Bi-polar disorder, PTSD, autism and dyslexia offer fresh interpretations of mythological, and other, figures. For instance, can one offer a reading of the Olympian gods through the prism of autism to look from a fresh angle on the special interests pursued by each of them?
What is disability studies? 

Among the various models are the following two:
  • Firstly, and now outmoded: the medical model, whereby a disability is a disorder that affects a particular individual.
  • Secondly, the social model, according to which disability is a social construction. This comes with a major shift in thinking - away from the 'medical model' that holds that individuals are disabled, and as such need to make adjustments to fit in with society, and towards a notion that it is actually society that does the disabling.
So it is not that disabled people need to change, but that society needs to change in order to make provision for disabled persons.  This has come with a change in terminology away from 'people with disabilities' to 'disabled persons'. For example, rather than talking of a 'person with dyslexia', instead one might talk of a 'dyslexic person'.  So - from being viewed as an individual, pathological disorder, disability can be regarded as a social construction, and with this there has come to be a recognition that the experience of disability will differ between persons, even those labelled similarly, e.g. as dyslexic or autistic. 
 
A consequence of this turn to a constructivist approach to disability has been that, to understand more deeply how disability is socially constructed, a place can be found for the study of disability across disciplines, including anthropology, literature, art, and history.  From the perspective of history, there is the potential to explore how disability was regarded in different periods, including in antiquity.  The potential for classics to contribute here is huge, when for example disability is 'good to think with' in myth, perceptions of tyranny etc - as I shall outline later.
 
One of the major studies to date is that of Rose's Staff of Oedipus of a decade ago which looks for what disability meant in the ancient Greek world, and what the experiences were of disabledpersons.  Rose situates her work in relation to the project of historicising disability. Her findings include:
  1. that there must have been a range of body types beyond the sculptural ideal, including from war injuries
  2. that the practice of killing deformed babies was less widespread than previously thought
  3. that Hephaistos provides a useful example of a different kind of body
  4. that the split that we today perceive between disabled and non-disabled people was not present in ancient Greece - shown, for instance, by the range of roles open to disabled people
  5. that our views cannot be mapped onto the past: our categories were not used to classify people
  6. that ancient Greece was forward looking: disability was not used to mark difference.
There is a fit with the argument of Fiedler  that we are anachronistic if we assume a consistent way of seeing disabled bodies in antiquity and today. According to Fiedler, the discussion of disability in antiquity has been anachronistic in assuming that  ‘the strangely formed body has represented absolute Otherness in all times and places since human history began’ (1996: xiii). 

Dolmage, meanwhile, looks for different kinds of bodies in antiquity: at least in myth, such as:
  • The monstrous body of Medusa
  • The lost body of Metis
  • The disabled body of Hephaistos
On the ‘import of bias’ onto ancient thinking about disability, v. Dolmage 2006; Dolmage 2009: 6-7.
 
Such an approach is readily possible as seen by two diverging ways of approach Hephaistos, for example, firstly that he was inferior to Athena (because her birth honoured her father while that of Hephaistos dishonoured his mother) and secondly that his birth rendered him klutos ('glorious'). I'll quote from my forthcoming book on Athena as 'traitor' and 'trickster':
       In the Homeric Hymn to Apollo, Hera’s fury is vented at Zeus for his successful attempt to ‘dishonour’ her (3.312) with the birth of ‘glaukopis Athena who is foremost among all the blessed gods’ (314-5) while ‘my son Hephaistos, to whom I gave birth, was shrivelled in foot and a shame to me’.  This god, according to his mother is, moreover, ‘weakly among the blessed gods’ (316-7). However, the Hephaistos presented in the Theogony of Hesiod is not an inferior being but a god who, as ‘glorious’ klutos (927), stands unequalled among the gods in the expertise that makes him ‘more skilled in techne than all the descendents of Ouranos’.
An aside: why isn't Athena disabled but the exemplar of hygieia, (good health, whence our 'hygiene'), which as I'll consider presently could be opposed to 'disability'?
 
There is, however, a source which does point to a classification more akin to ours: Lysias 24: On the refusal of a pension to the invalid.  The speaker has been accused of illegally drawing the pension granted to hoi adunatoi, a phrase which is generally translated 'the disabled'.  The pension was, according to the Ath. Pol., granted to those who were in poverty, and 'incapacitated by a bodily infirmity' (Constitution of the Athenians 49.4 check tr.!).  A contrast is drawn being hygiainos ('in good health') and adunatos ('disabled': Lys. 24.13); such persons should be regarded, according to Lysias, as deserving of pity.
 
Moreover, various sources for archaic tyrants and colonists fit the 'medical' model rather than the more constructivist social model underscoring Rose's work.  In the words of Ogden's title and cover-image they are 'crooked' literally and metaphorically.  Battus, the founder of Cyrene, was cured of his stammer when he shouted at a lion in the countryside outside the Cyrene who then fled.  See here, Gurentch's article.  Labda, the mother of Cypselus the tyrant of Corinth, was named as such, supposedly, after the capital letter lambda, because her feet turned outwards.  She was a member of the ruling Bacchiad clan, but, because of her deformity, was - exceptionally - married outside the clan; the child of her marriage, at once of Bacchiad descent and an outsider, usurps power.
 
Aside: it's worth thinking about how tyrants are exceptional individuals, both greater and lesser than ordinary mortals, and disability is one of the aspects that marks them as such.
 
Some prelimary conclusions:

There are two potential benefits to studying disability in antiquity, or to studying antiquity through the prism of disability:
  1. To shed fresh light upon the classical world
  2. To add to work in Disability Studies on how to historicise disability.
Also:
  • The thesis of Rose cannot be upheld insofar as there were provisions or disabled people as a category as well as a sense of the disabled body as a different one, whether inferior or superior.  The medical model can be applied more readily than the social one. Where physical disability is concerned, one can draw the same kind of conclusion as for so many groups in ancient Greek life (e.g. slaves, rape victims): that the ancient world was not a nice place. 
  • But the social model can be applied as follows: The study of disability in ancient Greece does not need to focus solely on the experiences of specific disabled persons.  Also of interest is how disability was constructed to reflect on such issues as health, skill (and so 'ability'), difference and status. 
  • And also of interest - and as touched on in this posting - is how far the ancient Greek world can be read in relation to work on disability, e.g. autism, PTSD and learning differences.

Some links and references (not yet standardised...)
  • For work largely in German but also with plenty of references to work in English: http://www.disabilitystudies.de/literatur.html
  • The Leeds Centre of Disability Studies includes lots of reading material: http://disability-studies.leeds.ac.uk/
  • Rose's work arguing for Greece as “forward-thinking“ in terms of disability, and not using disability as a marker of difference: Martha L. Rose. The Staff of Oedipus. Transforming Disability in Ancient Greece. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 2003.  See the review in a Disability Studies journal at: http://www.dsq-sds.org/article/view/875/1050
  • Fiedler, L. 1996. ‘Foreword’, in R.G. Thomson ed. Freakery: Cultural spectacles of the extraordinary body. New York: New York University Press: i-xv.
  • Dolmage, J. 2006. ‘Breathe upon us an even flame: Hephaestus, history, and the body of rhetoric’. Rhetoric Review 25.2: 119-40.
  • Dolmage, J. 2009. ‘Metis, mêtis, mestiza, Medusa: rhetorical bodies across rhetorical traditions’. Rhetoric Review 28.1: 1-28.
  • Ogden, D. The Crooked Kings of Ancient Greece, London: Duckworth 1997.
  • Gurentch, Z. “The tongue´s breakdance: theory, poetry and the critical body, available“ at: http://danm.ucsc.edu/~abtollef/Physical_Poetry/toungue%20body.pdf


 
 

No comments: